The reasonable doubt



1.    The origins of “reasonable doubt”
 
The origins of “reasonable doubt” lie in a forgotten world of pre-modern Christian theology, a world whose concerns were quite different from our own.

At its origins, the “reasonable doubt” rule was not intended to perform the function we ask it to perform today: It was not primarily intended to protect the accused. Instead, it had a significantly different, and distinctly Christian, purpose: The “reasonable doubt” formula was originally concerned with protecting the souls of the jurors against damnation. Convicting an innocent defendant was regarded, in the older Christian tradition, as a potential mortal sin. The purpose of the “reasonable doubt” instruction was to address this frightening possibility, reassuring jurors that they could convict the defendant without risking their own salvation, as long as their doubts about guilt were not “reasonable.” It is only if we see the rule in this original context that we can grasp its significance: The rule was simply never designed to protect the accused, nor even to serve as a standard of proof in the proper sense of the term.

The medieval office-holders faced the risk of damnation if they committed sin in the course of their official acts. Those risks confronted judges just as they faced to all officeholders.
Indeed, the problems of judges were considered exceptionally important, and commanded considerable attention. As medieval church lawyers put it, any sinful misstep committed by a judge in the course of judging and rules had to be developed to shield the judge from the consequences of his own official acts. This was especially true any time a judge imposed “blood punishments”—i.e., execution and mutilation, the standard criminal punishments of pre-nineteenth-century law.

Now, when it came to inflicting blood punishments, pre-modern Christian theology turned in particular on the problem of “doubt.” “Doubt” about the facts presented a real danger to the soul of the individual judge: “Doubt” was the voice of an uncertain conscience, and in principle it had to be obeyed. Such was the rule laid down in particular by the standard “safer way” school of Christian moral theology: “In cases of doubt,” as the “safer way” formula ran, “the safer way is not to act at all.”

This doctrine was applied to judging as it was to all other acts involving the individual conscience: As a typical French “dictionary of conscience” explained the standard Christian law in the eighteenth century, “In every case of doubt, where one’s salvation is in peril, one must always take the safer way. . . . A judge who is in doubt must refuse to judge.” A judge who sentenced an accused person to a blood punishment while experiencing “doubt” about guilt committed a mortal sin, and thus put his own salvation at risk. These were injunctions that were applied to judges in every part of western Christendom, from Spain to Germany, from Italy to England.

The history of the “reasonable doubt” rule is the history of English struggles with these universal western Christian challenges. Common law jurors were Christians, and they were Christians who engaged in acts of judgment. During the Middle Ages English criminal jurors did not yet face the worst dangers involved in such acts: Medieval criminal juries were not compelled to enter the general verdict of “guilty,” and therefore were not compelled to put their souls at risk. But in the early modern period, the moral dangers of judging became acute for English criminal jurors. As an eighteenth-century guide to the Englishman’s civic duties ominously reminded its readers: “The Office and Power of these Juries is Judicial, they only are the Judges from whose Sentence the Indicted are to expect Life or Death.”  Yet within the Christian tradition this was an “Office and Power” fraught with danger. To be a juror was potentially to “build yourself a mansion in Hell”—“to pawn [your] Soul,” as a famous seventeenth-century pamphlet put it. There is plenty of evidence that Christian jurors took this quite seriously, especially at the end of the eighteenth century. As the moral philosopher William Paley described the situation in 1785, jurors experienced “a general dread lest the charge of innocent blood should lie at their doors.” Jurors simply did not want to convict, Paley complained: In their “weak timidity,” they held it “the part of a safe conscience not to condemn any man, whilst there exists the minutest possibility of his innocence.”

It was in response to such juror “timidity” and “dread” that the “reasonable doubt” standard introduced itself into the common law in the 1770s and especially 1780s. 


It was in response to such juror “timidity” and “dread” that the “reasonable doubt” standard introduced itself into the common law in the 1770s and especially 1780s. 

Paley’s 1785 description of jurors who wished to preserve a “safe conscience” was exactly correct: English Christian jurors of the 1780s, following the standard precepts of “safer way” theology, often wished to take the “surest side” or the “safer way,” refusing to convict the accused where they experienced “any degree of doubt.” The same was true on the American side of the Atlantic: As John Adams reminded the jurors in the Boston Massacre trials in 1770, repeating language of moral theology that dated back to the Middle Ages: “[w]here you are doubtful never act: that is, if you doubt of the prisoner’s guilt, never declare him guilty; that is always the rule, especially in cases of life.” It was in the face of such religiously motivated reluctance to convict that the “reasonable doubt” rule arose, taking its now-familiar form during the 1780s. Christian moral theology had always left some room to ignore doubts that were not “reasonable.”

English criminal justice embraced this, aiming to persuade jurors that they could convict without risk to the safety of their salvation, as long as their “doubts” were not “reasonable.”
Such is the origin of “reasonable doubt.” As it suggests, the “beyond a reasonable doubt” standard was not originally designed to make it more difficult for jurors to convict. As thoughtful historians have sometimes recognized, it was designed to make conviction easier, by assuring jurors that their souls were safe if they voted to condemn the accused. In its original form, it had nothing to do with maintaining the rule of law in the sense that we use the phrase, and nothing like the relationship we imagine to the values of liberty. It was the product of a world troubled by moral anxieties that no longer trouble us much at all. All of this makes it unsurprising that our law should find itself in a state of confusion today. We are asking the “reasonable doubt” standard to serve a function that it was not originally designed to serve, and it does its work predictably badly.

Indeed, our difficulties in understanding the “reasonable doubt” rule are the result of a failure of historical memory. We have forgotten that legal procedures in the premodern world were not like legal procedures today. They did not always aim only at achieving certainty and proof in cases where the guilt of the offender was uncertain. Nor did they aim only at providing procedural safeguards for the accused. Instead, they were often designed to help relieve the judge’s own anxieties about the dangers surrounding the act of judging. As James Fitzjames Stephen, the pioneering nineteenth-century historian of the criminal law, famously put it, pre-modern judges often dreaded “the responsibility—which to many men would appear intolerably heavy and painful—of deciding . . . upon the guilt or innocence of the prisoner.” They dreaded this responsibility so much that they avoided entering verdicts if at all possible, or else sought to diminish their personal responsibility in other ways. They were not seeking proof so much as they were seeking moral comfort.

To understand this, we must begin by recognizing how authentically disquieting the act of judgment could seem in the pre-modern world. Pre-modern judges did indeed face “heavy and painful” dangers. Not all of these dangers were spiritual. Sometimes they were legal: In medieval Italy, for example, judges were subject to civil and criminal liability for incorrect judgments. English jurors faced similar legal threats until 1670.

On a grosser level, the physical well-being of a judge was sometimes threatened in the past, just as it is still sometimes threatened today: The pre-modern judge who condemned a person might easily become the target of vengeance by that person’s family or associates. The world of today, in which most judges can simply leave the courtroom behind with comparatively little fear for their lives or livelihoods, is a very modern world.



2.    History of the reasonable doubt standard in the United States
 
In the US, various terms used to describe, explain, and analogize “reasonable doubt” were oftentimes approved in one case, and then overturned in subsequent cases involving substantially similar jury instructions. Up until the mid-19th century, vague formulas such as “moral certainty” created more confusion than clarity.

In 1970, in the seminal case of In re Winship, the US Supreme Court constitutionalized the reasonable standard of proof, holding that it was protected by the Due Process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to the US Constitution. The Court put forward two reasons. First, the Court reasoned that the reasonable doubt standard “is a prime instrument for reducing the risk of convictions resting on factual error” since “[it] provides concrete substance for the presumption of innocence, because of the possibility that he may lose his liberty upon conviction and because of the certainty that he would be stigmatized by the conviction.” Second, the Court reasoned that the reasonable doubt standard is “indispensable to command the respect and confidence of the community in applications of the criminal law,” giving individuals the confidence that “[their] government cannot adjudge [them] guilty of a criminal offence without convincing a proper fact-finder of [their] guilt with utmost certainty.”

Though the reasonable doubt standard was constitutionalized in In re Winship, there was little consideration of its operation and effect. The US Supreme Court did not define reasonable doubt, nor did it address the issue of whether and to what extent, the reasonable doubt standard should be explained to the jury. The failure to address the relationship or conflict between the reasonable doubt and the ideas reflected in such terms as certainty and moral certainty, has led the US Supreme Court to revisit the issue and discuss the reasonable doubt instructions several subsequent cases, but to no avail.

Overall, the US Supreme Court’s case law on the reasonable doubt standard boils down to little analysis of the actual meaning of reasonable doubt and the effect the reasonable doubt instruction has on juries.



3.    Definition of the reasonable doubt standard in the Anglo-Saxon world
 
There is no definitive definition on what amounts to reasonable doubt that is universally applied to the common law systems. Nor is there a consistent definition applied within any one common law jurisdiction. Common law systems, where jury instructions are central to criminal trials – because the jury has to weigh the evidence and decide the facts – have not yet developed a definition that escapes criticism.

In the US, the definition of reasonable doubt varies not only from state to state, but also among the Federal Circuit Courts of Appeal. Some jurisdictions adopt pattern criminal jury instructions, which provide a definition of sufficient clarity to enable an ordinary juror to understand it and apply it. For example, Pattern Criminal Jury Instructions of the US Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit provide:

Proof beyond a reasonable doubt does not mean proof beyond all possible doubt. Possible doubts or doubts based purely on speculation are not reasonable doubts. A reasonable doubt is a doubt based on reason and common sense. It may arise from the evidence, the lack of evidence, or the nature of the evidence. Proof which is so convincing that you would not hesitate to rely and act on it in making the most important decisions in your own lives. If you are convinced that the government has proved the defendant guilty beyond a reasonable doubt, say so by returning a guilty verdict. If you are not convinced, say so by returning a not guilty verdict.

By contrast, the US Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit contains no instruction regarding the definition of the reasonable doubt standard. In United States v. Glass, the Seventh Circuit stated that attempts to explain the term “reasonable doubt” do not usually result in making it any clearer to the minds of the jury. In Glass, the Court stated:
That is precisely why this circuit’s criminal jury instructions forbid them. ‘Reasonable doubt’ must speak for itself. Jurors know what is ‘reasonable’ and are quite familiar with the meaning of ‘doubt.’ Judges’ and lawyers’ attempts to inject other amorphous catch-phrases into the ‘reasonable doubt’ standard, such as ‘matter of the highest importance,’ only muddy the water.

This jury attested to that. It is, therefore, inappropriate for judges to give an instruction defining ‘reasonable doubt,’ and it is equally inappropriate for trial counsel to provide their own definition. Trial counsel may argue that the government has the burden of proving the defendant's guilt ‘beyond a reasonable doubt,’ but they may not attempt to define ‘reasonable doubt.’

Similar to the Seventh Circuit’s position, the United Kingdom Court of Criminal Appeal (now superseded by the Court of Appeal of England and Wales) advised lower courts judges against providing a definition of what amounts to proof beyond a reasonable doubt. Lord Chief Justice Goddard of the Court of Criminal Appeal remarks in Regina v. Summers (1952) are telling:

I have never yet heard any court give a satisfactory definition of what is a “reasonable doubt,” and it would be very much better if that expression was not used. Whenever a court attempts to explain what is meant by it, the explanation tends to result in confusion rather than clarity.

Canadian appellate courts have also declined to define reasonable doubt.



4.    Reasonable doubt in the practice of the European Court of Human Rights
 
In 1969, the European Commission of Human Rights rendered what appears to be the first definition of the reasonable doubt standard in what is known as the Greek case.

The Commission was tasked with deciding what standard of proof to apply in evaluating evidence related to allegations of torture under Article 3 of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR). The Commission held that allegations of breaches of Article 3 must be proved beyond a reasonable doubt, defining it as “not a doubt based on a merely theoretical possibility or raised in order to avoid a disagreeable conclusion, but a doubt for which reasons can be given drawn from the facts presented.”

Nine years later, the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) reaffirmed and elaborated this definition in Ireland v. United Kingdom (1978). It added that proof of beyond reasonable doubt may follow from “the coexistence of sufficiently strong, clear, and concordant inferences, or of similar unrebutted presumptions of fact.”

This definition, although not very detailed or precise, sets the minimum standard to which States party to the ECHR and subject to the ECtHR’s jurisdiction are obliged to adhere. Of course, nothing prevents national legislators from developing a standard that provides more protection than the minimum standard allowable under ECtHR jurisprudence.



5.    Burden of proof
 
In common law systems the term “burden of proof” can have two meanings: the burden of persuasion and the burden of production. Distinguishing between these two meanings is important and necessary due to the distribution of functions between the judge and the jury. Generally, the trial judge decides questions of law, whereas the jury decides questions of fact. This explains why juries are referred to as the fact finder (also known as the trier of fact), a term that also applies to judges when conducting a non-jury trial, also known as a bench trial.

Throughout the trial proceedings, the judge instructs the jury on its obligations, the various rights afforded to the accused, how to weigh the credibility of witnesses, and how to assess other evidentiary matters, such as the testimony from the accused, expert witness testimony, conflicts of interest, and character evidence. At the end of the trial and before the jury deliberates, the judge gives the jury final instructions on what it must consider before reaching a verdict.

The judge instructs the jury that the burden of proof is always on the prosecution and that the accused has the right to rely upon the failure or inability of the prosecution to establish beyond a reasonable doubt any essential element of a crime charged.

The defense is not required to present any evidence, save for when raising a defense, and, even then, the evidence need not rise to the reasonable doubt standard. The defense can remain silent during the trial proceedings yet still argue that the prosecution failed to prove the charges beyond a reasonable doubt. This refers to the first meaning of the burden of proof, also characterized as the burden of persuasion, risk of non-persuasion, the legal or persuasive burden, or the ultimate burden – a party’s obligation to prove an assertion or charge. When it comes to the ultimate issue of guilt, in common law systems the prosecution bears the burden.

The second meaning of the burden of proof, characterized as the burden of production or the burden of going forward or evidential burden, refers to the order of presentation of evidence prescribed by law.

This meaning generally applies when the defense opts to raise an affirmative defense or claim an alibi. In other words, the burden of production specifies who is required to present the requisite evidence in order for the fact-finder to decide on the affirmative defense or claim of alibi. The burden of production can also be referred to as the duty of passing the judge, since it is the trier-of-law (the judge) who decides whether a party has met its burden of production for the issue to go before the fact-finder (the jury).



Conclusions

The reasonable doubt standard, together with the in dubio pro reo principle and the presumption of innocence, is the bedrock of criminal trials in common law systems.

Whatever catapulted the reasonable doubt standard to the forefront as the preeminent and universally accepted standard of proof in common law systems is no more relevant today than the historical backdrop of how intimate conviction (generally described as the personal opinion the judge forms after inward reflection on the evidence discussed by the parties at trial) became the standard of proof in civil law systems. It does little in resolving the persistent difficulties in framing a clear, concise and consistent definition of the standard. 

The US jurisprudence is rather telling: recurrent problems in defining and applying the reasonable doubt standard persist, as the different US Circuit Courts of Appeal accept a wide variety of instructions on the reasonable doubt standard.

Arguably, the definitional differences between the reasonable doubt standard and intimate conviction standard are a matter of semantics. There appears to be little, if any, difference in the quality of proof between these two different standards. Both require application of the in dubio pro reo principle, resulting in a high degree of proof tantamount to near certainty, eschewing fanciful or inconsequential doubts.

Just as for civil law judges there should be no real dilemma in discerning the qualitative substance of evidence required to be satisfied of the guilt of an accused to an intimate conviction, the lack of a concise and universally accepted definition of reasonable doubt should not pose a dilemma for judges in judge-tried cases in common law systems. Judges, by virtue of their training and knowledge of the law and rules of evidence, are expected to assess the testimonial and documentary evidence presented during a criminal trial and apply the requisite law in determining whether the prosecution has met his or her burden of proving the elements of the charged crimes.

The reasonable doubt standard does not operate in the abstract. It is intrinsic to a number of other mechanisms, from rules of procedure and evidence to a set of jury instructions invoked throughout the trial. Were jury trials to be introduced in a hybrid system, numerous obstacles and challenges can be anticipated, such as:

-       -Procedures would have to be developed to select juries free of bias, and to keep them that way for the duration of trial and deliberation;

-       -Formal rules of procedure and evidence would have to be developed to protect the jury fact-finder from prejudicial and other inadmissible evidence;

-      - A list of evidentiary objections would be required to ensure that the rules of procedure and evidence were being implemented;

-       -The judges would have to be trained in addressing the evidentiary objections while assessing the evidence contemporaneously as it is presented at trial;

-       -The lawyers would have to be trained in making the timely and specific objections at trial to make a record for appeal;

-       -Clear instructions for the jurors would have to be developed to guide the jurors at each phase of the trial; and

-       -A clear, concise and easily understood definition of reasonable doubt would need to be developed.

Another critical challenge is the lack of transparency. Jurors do not explain their verdicts. They deliberate secretly. They do not give an accounting on what evidence was accepted or rejected, what weight was afforded to any particular evidence or testimony, the credibility of witnesses or how they reached their individual decision on the evidence.

Finally, aside from the challenges already noted, there is also a host of issues related to resources that must be considered, such as:

-       -Retrofitting the courthouses and courtrooms to accommodate jurors, compensating jurors for their time (similar to paying lay judges who are currently striking in demanding higher fees);

-       -Imposing disciplinary measures on those unwilling to respond to jury summons;

-       -Costs for summonsing and holding disciplinary hearings on causes for not being sanctioned for failing to respond to summons; and

-       -The added time it would take to conduct jury trials, which by all accounts and measures, take considerably longer than judge-tried cases.




Bibliography: 

The Origins of "Reasonable Doubt." James Q. Whitman

Gruesome Evidence and Emotion: Anger, Blame, and Jury Decision-Making. David A.Bright. Jane Goodman-Delahunty

Reasonable Certainty and Reasonable Doubt. Henry L. Chambers, Jr.

Beyond "Reasonable Doubt.” Jon O. Newman

The Constitutional Status of the Reasonable Doubt Rule. Donald A. Dripps

Conference and roundtable discussion "Doubt in favour of the defendant, guilty beyond reasonable doubt". Michael G. Karnavas






Comments

Popular Posts