Ignorance of Law is no Excuse
Introduction
“Ignorance
of the law is no excuse,” says an ancient legal nostrum.
The
reason for it is simple enough: If ignorance could excuse any crime, then
ignorance might excuse every crime. Rather than impose on the legal system the
obligation to prove a defendant’s knowledge of the law — with the defendant’s
incentive running in the opposite direction, toward ignorance of the law — the
legal system assigns to itself no obligation in this regard. Upon which
defendants find that they have an enormous incentive to know what the law is
and to comport themselves accordingly.
This is not
necessarily as crazy as it sounds. It doesn’t assume that the accused did know
the law; no one knows all the laws. No one ever has. It simply says that
ignorance doesn’t matter.
How can
that be defensible? In the old days, it wasn’t so difficult. As Cicero wrote:
There is a true law, a right reason,
conformable to nature, universal, unchangeable, eternal, whose commands urge us
to duty, and whose prohibitions restrain us from evil… This law cannot be
contradicted by any other law, and is not liable either to derogation or
abrogation.
Neither
the senate nor the people can give us any dispensation for not obeying this
universal law of justice. It needs no other expositor and interpreter than our
own conscience. It is not one thing at Rome and another at Athens; one thing
today and another tomorrow; but in all times and nations this universal law
must for ever reign, eternal and imperishable.
Everyone
can know the universal law by use of right reason. And by means of living at
Rome or Athens, say, a citizen could become habituated to local modes of
conduct, and these would supply whatever content the natural law did not.
Much
manmade law is merely customary, and this type of law is neither an
instantiation of the natural law nor a violation of it. Still, though, some
customs may be needed to facilitate commerce and peace.
To learn
these customs, whenever an individual entered into a new line of work, or into
any other new endeavour, we could expect that he would observe carefully the
actions of others who were already engaged in it; in general, he would conform
himself to their pattern. In the process he would come to appreciate the inner
logic of being a rope maker at Athens, before he attempted to make and sell
rope at Athens himself.
So while
it is impossible for any individual, even a lawyer or a judge, to sit down and
write out the entire law code, it could still be relatively defensible to hold
individuals accountable for their violations of it. The law was an expression
of two things that individuals ought to know, namely the universal law and the
particulars of one’s own time and place.
But this
is in a sense a house of cards: What if custom and the universal law conflict?
Which one prevails?
Cicero
says that it’s the custom that must give way, but it is not clear that it
actually will give way in any particular instance. Bad customs can endure for
centuries, sometimes.
Or what
if the written law is ambiguous, as applied to a particular case? What if one
law conflicts with another, or if there is a dispute over which part of a large
customary legal code governs a particular circumstance? What if two parts of
universal law appear to conflict with one another? Or if there is a question
about which part of universal law is applicable in a particular case?
To
resolve these types of conflicts is the work of a judiciary.
1. The Roman Experience
The
ignorantia legis maxim is of ancient vintage, dating back at least as far as
the days of the Roman Empire. Legal scholars have described the Roman maxim
primarily as a concept of civil law, which was founded on the straightforward
(if fictitious) rationale that the law was “certain and capable of being
ascertained. “Thus, in litigation, positive proof of a citizen’s knowledge of
the law’s requirements or proscriptions was not required. Rather, citizens were
presumed to be familiar with the law, for it was not the function of the Roman
law “to aid the fools."
Even from
these early beginnings, however, application of the maxim was subject to
important, if limited, exceptions when the law was not, in fact, definite and
knowable. Despite widespread acceptance of the maxim, Roman law permitted
certain groups of persons to claim ignorance of the law as a defense. The very
young, for example, were considered to be incapable of comprehending important
aspects of the law and thus were permitted to excuse their deviant behavior by
claiming ignorance of the law’s requirements or restraints.
So too
might disenfranchised women, soldiers away from home, and “peasants and other
persons of small intelligence” escape penalty by claiming unfamiliarity with
certain of the law’s commands. The common link between these disparate groups
appears to be that they were all thought to lack some essential quality that
would enable them to appraise or know the law, such as aptitude (women and
members of the underclass), maturity (children) or notice of the law’s
enactment (absent soldiers). Latitude for error was accorded these people so as
not to penalize them for failing to meet legal obligations that were, to them,
either unknown or unknowable.
The Roman
reprieve extended only so far, however. Although these disparate groups of
Roman citizens were considered to be incapable of knowing the ius civile (the
body of civil law that governed Roman relations), they were expected to know
and comply with the us gentium (the system of laws that “natural reason” had
settled among all persons everywhere). As generously put much later by legal
commentator John Austin, because these persons did not fall within the state of
“general imbecility,” they could be expected to know the ius gentium, which was
based on principles of natural reason presumptively understood by all.
2. The Maxim in England
In
England, the maxim took on a less forgiving cast. Although it appears that the
maxim originated in civil actions under Roman law, the English courts permitted
it to control the outcome of criminal actions as well. In addition, the English
common law courts defined the distinction between claims of ignorance or
mistakes of law and mistakes of fact. Mistakes of pertinent fact were generally
considered to provide a defense, while mistakes of law generally were not.
Early
commentators on the English maxim defended it on the same rationale that the
Romans had employed: the law was “definite and knowable” so it was fair to
demand the compliance of anyone who possessed sufficient capacity to know it.
While the very young and the mentally incompetent were afforded some latitude
for error under this rationale, all other subjects of the realm were obligated
to know the law, and presumed to do so. Later, however, as reflected by the
passage at the start of this Article, British legal theorists began to offer
utilitarian rationales for the principle—the fear that without the maxim the
defense of ignorance of the law would be abused (all would claim ignorance to
avoid punishment) and the concern that feigned claims would be impossible to
refute.
Despite
the English devotion to the ignorantia legis maxim, important (though limited)
exceptions to the maxim existed under English law, just as they had under Roman
law. One scholar noted: “In both [the Roman and English] systems considerations
of equity induced the courts to deviate from the rule if arising cases did not
expressly warrant its application.” Departures were also granted in criminal
cases when the doctrine of mens rea required that they be, such as when
particular specific intent crimes required proof of an intent that was negative
by the accused’s lack of knowledge of his culpability.
3. The Maxim in the United States
The
ignorantia juris maxim currently in place in the United States grew out of this
venerable ancestry. Broad and early acceptance of the maxim is found in
numerous cases. As with the Roman and British versions, the American version of
the principle was frequently articulated in lofty terms: every person “of
reasonable understanding is presumed to know the law, and to act upon the
rights which it confers or supports,” and “it is culpable negligence in him to
do an act...and then to set up his ignorance of law as a defence.”
Legal
theorists continued to study the maxim and proposed three additional rationales
in its support. Rejecting Austin’s argument that problems of proof justified
the maxim, Oliver Wendell Holmes proposed an alternative utilitarian rationale:
“To admit the excuse at all would be to encourage ignorance where the law-maker
has determined to make persons know and obey, and justice to the individual is
rightly outweighed by the larger interests on the other side of the scales.” In
Holmes’s view, punishing offenders who acted in ignorance of the law would
achieve optimal societal knowledge of, and compliance with, the law. Thus,
adherence to the maxim would promote a culture of legal literacy, while a
retreat from it, even if in the interests of individuated justice, would give
rise to a community of legal simpletons.
Professor Jerome Hall later challenged Holmes’s view and proposed that
the maxim was justified by a more fundamental rationale—the rationale of
legality. Hall contended that ignorance of the law claims could not be
permitted for to do so would contradict the principle of legality, elevating
offenders’ perceptions of the law above the law itself. Under the legality
principle, when an accused fails to know that her conduct violates a law,
whether because she failed to inform herself of the law’s existence or its
application to her behaviour, or because she misunderstood or disagreed with
its prescribed meaning, the law should be unforgiving.
Finally,
Professor Henry M. Hart postulated that the “essential rationale” of the “much
misunderstood” maxim is that any member of the community who engages in
intrinsically wrongful, prohibited acts “without knowing that they are criminal
is blameworthy, as much for his lack of knowledge as for his actual conduct.”
Using
murder as an example of such an inherently wrongful act, Hart argued that even
if an offender somehow lacked knowledge that the murderous act violated a
specific criminal law, her conduct would still be blameworthy and deserving of
criminal punishment as much because she did not know that murder was wrong as
because she took another’s life.
Hart warned, however, that the maxim should
only be applied to rules that adequately reflect community attitudes or needs;
it should not be applied to an individual who offends a statute that punishes
conduct that is malum prohibitum (conduct that is wrong only because it is
illegal) rather than conduct that is malum in se (conduct that is intrinsically
wrongful).
American
courts have never agreed on a single rationale for the maxim. Some courts have
applied the maxim to preclude mistake of law claims on the ground that such
claims would arrest the administration of justice and provide a “shield for the
guilty.”
Other
jurists have cited the Holmesian view that the maxim is needed to promote
knowledge and compliance with the law. Still others have espoused Hall’s
principle of legality rationale, arguing that departures from the doctrine
would undermine “core standards of criminal behavior” that the criminal law
strives to secure. It is also not uncommon for combinations of the various
rationales to appear in a single judicial opinion.
The
inability of American jurists and commentators to agree on a single rationale
for the maxim has not precluded its application in the United States, but it
may help to explain the growing number of cases that have departed from the
maxim over time. Notwithstanding the wide variety of rationales that have been
used to support the application of the maxim in the United States, courts have
also deviated from the maxim, just as their forebears had done, when evidence
of bona fide ignorance or mistake has made criminal conviction (to them)
unfathomable, or the law itself has required forgiveness of an accused’s legal
error.
Thus, the
courts have sometimes (though not uniformly) held that an accused’s ignorance
of or mistake about a law is excusable if she fairly relied on some erroneous advice
from an official responsible for interpreting or enforcing that law. Ignorance
or mistakes of law might also be forgiven if it is determined that the accused
reasonably relied on a statute or judicial precedent later repealed or
overturned, or if the legislature failed to make the law adequately known or
knowable.
An
additional important subset of cases deviating from the maxim—and indeed, the
cases with which this Article is primarily concerned—consists of decisions in
which courts countenance ignorance or mistake of law claims because the claims
disprove an element of the offense the prosecution is obligated to establish.
These cases make clear that ignorance of the law will excuse if the law itself
permits it to do so.
Put
another way, the law itself may impose upon a prosecutor the obligation to
prove an accused’s knowledge of the law as a specific element of a particular
offense before a conviction may stand for its violation. For this reason, the
statement “ignorance of the law does not excuse” is decidedly deceptive. A more
precise statement of the maxim would be: “ignorance of the law is no defense
unless the law under which an accused is prosecuted makes knowledge of the law
an element of the offense.”
Determining
when the law does this can be a formidable task. As a matter of democratic
theory, because Congress, rather than the judiciary, makes the laws, Congress
must decide whether an offender’s ignorance of the law will or will not provide
a defense for each federal criminal enactment. When Congress makes its
intentions clear, the task of interpreting the statute should be relatively
straightforward. Problems arise when congressional intent is less evident. The
less clear Congress’s intent, the more daunting the courts’ interpretive task
becomes. In such situations, however, the maxim itself can be thought of as a
helpful rule of construction that favors a particular outcome (that knowledge
of illegality will not be an element) in the absence of evidence that Congress
desired a different result.
4. Ignorantia Legis
The
inconsistencies in the judicial pronouncements regarding vagueness and intent,
created by the struggle to prevent "unfair" convictions without
abandoning the concept that ignorance of the law cannot excuse, do more than
introduce disharmony into the theoretical structure of the criminal law. The
inconsistencies also reduce the effectiveness of these doctrines in securing
the fairness posited as their goal.
Both the doctrines and the goal of preventing
unfair imposition of criminal liability would be aided by recognizing lack of
knowledge of the law as a defense. The starting point must be acknowledgment
that this is a separate defense, not a matter to be accomplished by creating
special intent requirements for extraordinary cases. Indeed, the need for a
defense of ignorance separate from the law of intent is largely the result of
the difficulties faced by the Court with that area of the law since the advent
of regulatory crimes.
At common
law, the mens rea necessary to convict generally required that the government
show the defendant to have acted purposefully to bring about a harm, to have
known facts indicating that the harm would be a likely result of his action, or
to have acted without concern for whether the harm would follow. The
combinations of acts and harms to which these requirements applied were known
by the community to be proscribed; under the M'Naghten rule, failure to
appreciate the wrongfulness of one's act became the standard for insanity.
Given
common law crimes and intent requirements, Anglo-American courts thus found
knowledge of the law to be unnecessary to guard against unfair criminal
punishment. The rationales for and against igorantia legis, however, merit
examination in light of the changed nature of crimes and of mens rea
requirements.
5. The case against ignorantia legis
The case
against ignorantia legis is rarely argued, though criticisms of the doctrine
have been made by authors who support its retention. Along with such friendly
criticism, discussions of related doctrines provide a basis for a critique of
ignorantia legis.
Professor
Packer, for example, objects to the refusal of the Court to require mens rea;
his reasoning also could justify excusing by reason of ignorance. He found a
consensus that punishment of conduct without reference to intent is "both
inefficacious and unjust" because one who acts without "awareness of
the factors making [his conduct] criminal" is not to be deterred by
criminalizing such conduct, nor can he be held morally culpable."
Similarly, it may be argued that punishing a defendant who acted in ignorance
of the law is not likely to deter such conduct or to remove a socially dangerous
individual from the public domain; nor is such punishment just-the defendant's
ignorance does not mark his act as one properly calling for retribution.
The first
basis for criticism of ignorantia legis, then, is the inefficacy of punishing
the ignorant. Punishing persons who are not aware of the law making their
conduct criminal has no direct deterrent effect."
The act
for which such a defendant is punished could not have been deterred by the
potential for punishment of which he was unaware. Nor will such punishment
increase the ability of the law to deter him from repeating his illegal act.
Having been informed of the illegality of his conduct when charged with a
crime, the formerly ignorant offender will not be able to sustain a plea of
ignorance as to future similar illegal acts.
His
future conduct, thus, is shaped no differently by a law that punishes ignorant
offenders than by one that excuses them. Punishing ignorant offenders
nonetheless may have an indirect deterrent effect: the more persons punished,
the more notorious the crime. It seems unlikely, however, that deterrence by
notoriety would have much impact on commission of the relatively esoteric
regulatory crimes of which ignorance most often is pleaded, and whatever
deterrence is achieved must be weighed against its cost in deterring the
regulated activity.
Irrespective
of the balance between the benefit of the maxim in crimes prevented and its
cost in socially desirable activities discouraged, ignorantia legis appears
objectionable because it is unfair. The doctrine originally appears to have
been a qualified maxim, compatible with common notions of fairness.
Roman law
did not allow ignorance as a defense to actions under the ius gentium, the law
derived from the common customs of the Italian tribes and thought to embody the
basic rules of conduct any civilized person would deduce from proper reasoning.
But ignorance of the more compendious and less common-sense ius civile was a
defense allowed women, males less than 25 years old, soldiers, peasants, and
persons of small intelligence. A defendant not otherwise exempted from the
maxim's application apparently also was allowed a defense of ignorance of the
ius civile if he had not had the opportunity to consult counsel familiar with
the laws.
The
English law adopted ignorantia legis without the qualifications that, under
Roman law, tempered its harshness. Even so, for centuries the doctrine did not
appear to produce unjust results.
In Anglo-American civil law, damage to another
individual generally is a prerequisite to the defendant's liability. If damage
is not a formal element of liability, as in actions for trespass to land, an
intangible damage has occurred by definition if the required elements are
proved,"' and the award of "technical damages," to which
plaintiffs are limited unless actual damage may be presumed or shown, hardly
can be viewed as a stiff punishment.
The
imposition of civil liability thus can be justified as compensating the victim
for his loss; even if liability is not predicated on intent or negligence, the
individual made chiefly liable may be viewed as less "innocent" than
the person compensated, because the law of torts makes liable the person
thought best able to avoid the harm. As
applied to Anglo-American civil law, therefore, ignorantia legis seems
consistent with most rights of community members.
Until a
century ago, the application of the maxim to criminal law also seemed fair, as
a practical if not as a theoretical matter." Crimes initially were limited
to a relatively few offenses that every sane person old enough to become a
defendant reasonably could be presumed to know. Even as the number of offenses
expanded, their basic nature remained the same and the protection of mens rea
insured that noncompliance with the law was not punished unless both the
actor's intent and his act were blameworthy.
Given
this setting, the unquestioning acceptance of ignorantia legis by the foremost
legal minds of the 18th and 19th centuries is not surprising. Nor is it surprising
that as the criminal law increasingly came to be used as a sanction for various
regulatory measures designed to advance social and economic policies that were
connected only tangentially with community moral standards and as mens rea was
abandoned for these crimes, authors made greater efforts to examine and to
justify the doctrine. Because the criminal law is designed to enforce rules
rather than to compensate victims and therefore may punish commission of an act
even if no damage ensues, application of ignorantia legis to a wide variety of
crimes now appears offensive to the standards of fairness embodied in civil law
and expounded in discussions of other facets of criminal law.
A
relatively clear standard of fairness has been espoused, for example, with
regard to ex post facto laws, which impose or increase criminal sanctions for
acts not punishable when committed or alter the evidence necessary for
conviction. An early objection to
ignorantia legis was that it embodied the same unfairness as ex post facto
laws, at least when applied to ignorance of "positive regulations, not
taught by nature." ' An author surveying American customs and institutions
and comparing them with their European counterparts wrote in 1792:
Where a
man is ignorant of [a positive regulation], he is in the same situation as if
the law did not exist. To read it to him from the tribunal, where he stands
arraigned for the breach of it, is to him precisely the same thing as it would
be to originate it at the time by the same tribunal for the express purpose of
his condemnation.
In
Shevlin-Carpenter Co. v. Minnesota, the Supreme Court rejected this analogy,
declaring that "innocence cannot be asserted of an action which violates
existing law, and ignorance of the law will not excuse. The law in controversy
[punishing casual and involuntary trespass to state lands] has no ex post facto
element or effect in it."
Justice
McKenna's majority opinion did not attempt to evaluate the impact of the ex
post facto provision on ignorantia legis, but simply disposed of the analogy by
noting that ex post facto cases dealt with laws enacted after an individual's
action. The expansion of the ex post facto prohibition urged by the defendant
would have conflicted with ignorantia legis; the opinion treated the latter
maxim as though it were a constitutional mandate that had to be harmonized with
the ex post facto clause and refused the expansion.
Certainly,
more injustice derives from punishing a person for an offense that was not
criminal at the time of his act than from punishing him when he was unaware of
the act's illegality for another reason. Nonetheless, courts have recognized
that it is unfair to penalize one who cannot reasonably be expected to know
that his act is illegal, even if his ignorance is caused by something other
than the nonexistence of the law at the moment of defendant's assertedly
criminal act.'
Assessing
a vagueness challenge, the Supreme Court noted that imposing criminal liability
for violation of a statute that failed to define adequately the conduct it
prohibited "would be like sanctioning the practice of Caligula who
'published the law, but it was written in a very small hand, and posted up in a
corner, so that no one could make a copy of it.' In response to a defense of
ignorance argued before a federal circuit court in 1810, it was held that
sanctions could not be imposed for violation of a law passed before the
violation, when no copy of the law had been received at the place where the act
occurred until after the alleged offense."
Most
decisions that define a standard of fairness for punishing persons unaware of
the illegality of their actions do not involve the inaccessibility of the
statute making the actions criminal. In cases in which the vagueness of a
statute is alleged, criminal liability is not imposed for violation of an
existing, accessible statute unless the statute gives "fair warning."
ill Although decisions have not always been consistent with this rationale,
perhaps as the result of the influence of the rationale used to support
ignoratia legis, a number of cases clearly adhere to the principle that fair
warning of the criminality of an act is required before the commission of the
act is punishable."
In
Lambert v. California, the fair warning requirement was extended beyond
statutory specificity to include a reasonable likelihood that the defendant was
aware that the law required some particular conduct." The crux of the case against ignorantia legis
thus is embodied in this question: If it is inconsistent with basic notions of
fairness to penalize one for an act that, because of the nonexistence,
inaccessibility, or vagueness of the law, the actor believed legal when done,
why is it fair to punish one who is ignorant of the law for any other reason?
6. Ignorantia legis defended
Because
the courts have seemed willing to accept ignorantia legis as a fixed star, the
task of answering the question posed in opposition to the maxim has fallen
largely to academicians. Legal scholars have defended punishing those ignorant
of the law on numerous bases;"' from these, five major rationales appear.
Professor
Austin argued that to investigate a person's knowledge or ignorance of the law
in each case would hopelessly enmesh the courts in assessing virtually
insoluble problems. Although fear of presenting difficult factual issues to
courts may be a prime factor in continued judicial adherence to ignorantia
legis, the argument was rejected firmly by Holmes nearly a century ago and no
one has expressed much support for it since. Holmes "doubted whether a
person's knowledge of the law is any harder to investigate than many questions
which are gone into." Considering
the range of issues now put to judges or juries, particularly those relating to
a defendant's state of mind when "specific intent" crimes are
involved, it is difficult to quarrel with Holmes's observation.
The
second major justification for ignorantia legis, advanced in Blackstone's
Connnentaries and advocated most vigorously by Holmes, is that adherence to the
maxim deters crime. If ignorance
excused, according to Blackstone, the law could be "eluded with
impunity," or as Holmes put it, allowing a defense of ignorance would
encourage ignorance of the laws. Application of ignorantia legis, however,
cannot deter persons from repeating their offenses and can have only an
indirect effect on deterring others. Holmes used robbery and murder as examples
of crimes that should be discouraged for the good of the entire community; the
community, he reasoned, must sacrifice the individual to the public goal of
avoiding murder and robbery by punishing ignorant as well as knowing and
intentional transgressors so that all may know these acts to be illegal.
Robbery
and murder offer attractive examples, but ignorance of their criminality is
virtually impossible. Ignorance is most likely to be pleaded to regulatory
measures; examples, collected by Professor Perkins, of cases in which ignorance
of the law was pleaded, and rejected, as a defense include operating a gaming
device, betting on a horse race, conducting a raffle, and operating a saloon on
election day after the close of the election.
Although
defendants may harbor mistaken beliefs as to what constitutes robbery or murder
it is unlikely that any defendant would plead ignorance that these were
criminal, excpt incident to a plea of insanity. If regulatory, rather than
heinous, crimes are used as prototypes, the inadequacies of the deterrence
rationale may be seen clearly. Convictions for these crimes are unlikely to
receive the publicity accorded trials for murder, assault, embezzlement, and
other crimes that appeal to the popular sense of adventure, so that ignorantia
legis sacrifices the individual without educating, and hence without deterring,
the public. Further, if less heinous crimes are involved, surely the balance
between community and individual rights must be weighed more in favor of the
individual. Embodied in the Constitution is the notion that fairness to
individuals and orderliness in criminal proceedings are as much public
desiderata as prevention of harm to persons and property.
The third
justification for ignorantia legis is perhaps the best known and was the reason
originally given in American criminal cases for adoption of the doctrine: all
person are presumed to know the law. This presumption has been labelled
"absurd," and seems to ignore common experience if applied generally.
There undoubtedly are many crimes known to all competent, nonjuvenile members
of society, but even lawyers are not aware of all federal crimes, much less of
the multitude of state offenses. Beyond the illogic of such a presumption,
there is no reason it should be exempted from the scrutiny the Supreme Court
finds constitutionally mandated for other irrebuttable presumptions.
The Court
in 1969 reaffirmed the rule of Tot v. United States that the validity of a
presumption created by statute depends on a "rational connection between
the facts proved and the ultimate fact presumed." In Leary v. United States, the Court reversed
a conviction obtained by use of a presumption that possessors of marijuana knew
the marijuana to have been imported. The Court was unable to say "with
substantial assurance that the presumed fact is more likely than not to flow
from the proved fact on which it is made to depend." If the basis for ignorantia legis is the
presumption that anyone who commits a crime knows of the law he violated, that
presumption should be tested in each case by the standard of Tot and Leary. Use
of the presumption when it fails to satisfy that standard would violate due
process.
Another
rationale relied on to support punishment of persons ignorant of the law is
that such ignorance is blameworthy in itself. Holmes rejected this thesis,
noting that if it were the rationale for ignorantia legis a nonsensical result
would be achieved: failure to learn the law would be punished as severely as
failure to obey it.
Yet,
after examining other justifications for the doctrine, it is this argument for
ignorantia legis that seems most plausible. Holmes's objection to this
rationale assumes an incorrect factual predicate. Failure to know the law is
not punished unless it leads to a violation of the law; this coincidence, not
mere ignorance, is punished to the same extent as knowing and wilful violation
of the law. If ignorance of the law does not excuse because it is blameworthy,
the judge or jury in each case should ask whether the particular ignorance
claimed by a defendant is in fact blameworthy.
This
determination should not present any inordinate difficulties; the usual
question to be resolved would be whether a reasonable, prudent member of the
community of average intelligence would, be aware of the violated law. If
defendants were engaged in some regulated occupation and charged with violation
of a law regulating that occupation, a more rigorous test would be applied: the
fact-finder would determine whether the reasonable, prudent practitioner of
that -occupation would have known the law. As presently applied, however,
ignorantia legis makes no allowance for the possibility that ignorance of the
law is not always blameworthy. In light of the nature of crimes of which
ignorance is pleaded, the possibility that some ignorance may be culpable
cannot justify the maxim's application in so many cases where ignorance is
likely to be blameless.
A final
support for ignorantia legis, offered by Jerome Hall, is more concerned with
mistake of law than with ignorance of it.
Although Hall found the origin of ignorantia legis in the Roman notion
that law is definite and knowable,' he argued that defense of the doctrine must
rest on the unavoidable vagueness of the law.
Courts
have been designated as law declarers. If defendants' mistaken beliefs about
the lawfulness of certain conduct exempted the defendants from criminal
liability, Hall said, the function of the courts as law declarers would be
destroyed and the law would become what anyone thought it was. Hall's fear seems exaggerated. By exempting a
defendant from punishment on the ground that he operated under a mistaken
belief as to the law, courts would not abdicate their role in interpreting the
law any more than they do by excepting from punishment one who acted under an
impression of the law sufficiently far from correct to render the defendant
insane.
In either
case, the court declares what the law is but also declares that the defendant
is not criminally liable for violating it. The court thus remains law-declarer
in theory; allowing mistake of law to excuse will not impair the law-declaring
function of the courts in practice unless it impairs obedience to the law
declared. If allowing ignorance of a law to excuse would not lessen the
deterrent effect of the law, then allowing a mistaken belief concerning the
meaning of a law to excuse should have no greater adverse effect.
Further,
if a mistaken belief of law is blameworthy, in that the average community
member or professional would have learned the meaning of the law, the erroneous
belief should not excuse criminal conduct even if ignorantia legis is narrowed
to reflect its proper basis. A
requirement that mistake not be blameworthy substantially limits the number of
cases in which mistake could excuse.
Bibliography:
Ignorance of the Law: A Maxim Reexamined. Ronald A.
Cass
The Jurisprudence of wilfulness: An evolving
theory of excusable ignorance. Sharon L. Davies
Nonpayment of taxes: When ignorance of the law
is an excuse. Jon Strauss
The Death of a Maxim: Ignorance of Law is no
Excuse (Killed by Money, Guns and a Little Sex) Mark D. Yochum
Comments
Post a Comment